home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
- --------
- Nos. 91-744 and 91-902
- --------
- PLANNED PARENTHOOD OF SOUTHEASTERN
- PENNSYLVANIA, et al., PETITIONERS
- 91-744 v.
- ROBERT P. CASEY, et al., etc.
-
- ROBERT P. CASEY, et al., etc.,
- PETITIONERS
- 91-902 v.
- PLANNED PARENTHOOD OF SOUTHEASTERN
- PENNSYLVANIA et al.
- on writs of certiorari to the united states court of
- appeals for the third circuit
- [June 29, 1992]
-
- Justice Scalia, with whom the Chief Justice, Justice
- White, and Justice Thomas join, concurring in the
- judgment in part and dissenting in part.
- My views on this matter are unchanged from those I set
- forth in my separate opinions in Webster v. Reproductive
- Health Services, 492 U. S. 490, 532 (1989) (Scalia, J.,
- concurring in part and concurring in judgment), and Ohio
- v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health, 497 U. S. 502, 520
- (1990) (Akron II) (Scalia, J., concurring). The States may,
- if they wish, permit abortion-on-demand, but the Constitu-
- tion does not require them to do so. The permissibility of
- abortion, and the limitations upon it, are to be resolved like
- most important questions in our democracy: by citizens
- trying to persuade one another and then voting. As the
- Court acknowledges, -where reasonable people disagree the
- government can adopt one position or the other.- Ante,
- at 8. The Court is correct in adding the qualification that
- this -assumes a state of affairs in which the choice does not
- intrude upon a protected liberty,- ante, at 9-but the crucial
- part of that qualification is the penultimate word. A State's
- choice between two positions on which reasonable people
- can disagree is constitutional even when (as is often the
- case) it intrudes upon a -liberty- in the absolute sense.
- Laws against bigamy, for example-which entire societies
- of reasonable people disagree with-intrude upon men and
- women's liberty to marry and live with one another. But
- bigamy happens not to be a liberty specially -protected- by
- the Constitution.
- That is, quite simply, the issue in this case: not whether
- the power of a woman to abort her unborn child is a
- -liberty- in the absolute sense; or even whether it is a
- liberty of great importance to many women. Of course it is
- both. The issue is whether it is a liberty protected by the
- Constitution of the United States. I am sure it is not. I
- reach that conclusion not because of anything so exalted as
- my views concerning the -concept of existence, of meaning,
- of the universe, and of the mystery of human life.- Ibid.
- Rather, I reach it for the same reason I reach the conclu-
- sion that bigamy is not constitutionally protected-because
- of two simple facts: (1) the Constitution says absolutely
- nothing about it, and (2) the longstanding traditions of
- American society have permitted it to be legally pro-
- scribed. Akron II, supra, at 520 (Scalia, J., concurring).
- The Court destroys the proposition, evidently meant to
- represent my position, that -liberty- includes -only those
- practices, defined at the most specific level, that were
- protected against government interference by other rules of
- law when the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified,- ante,
- at 5 (citing Michael H. v. Gerald D., 491 U. S. 110, 127, n. 6
- (1989) (opinion of Scalia, J.). That is not, however, what
- Michael H. says; it merely observes that, in defining -lib-
- erty,- we may not disregard a specific, -relevant tradition
- protecting, or denying protection to, the asserted right,- 491
- U. S., at 127, n. 6. But the Court does not wish to be
- fettered by any such limitations on its preferences. The
- Court's statement that it is -tempting- to acknowledge the
- authoritativeness of tradition in order to -cur[b] the
- discretion of federal judges,- ante, at 5, is of course rhetoric
- rather than reality; no government official is -tempted- to
- place restraints upon his own freedom of action, which is
- why Lord Acton did not say -Power tends to purify.- The
- Court's temptation is in the quite opposite and more
- natural direction-towards systematically eliminating
- checks upon its own power; and it succumbs.
- Beyond that brief summary of the essence of my position,
- I will not swell the United States Reports with repetition of
- what I have said before; and applying the rational basis
- test, I would uphold the Pennsylvania statute in its
- entirety. I must, however, respond to a few of the more
- outrageous arguments in today's opinion, which it is beyond
- human nature to leave unanswered. I shall discuss each of
- them under a quotation from the Court's opinion to which
- they pertain.
-
- -The inescapable fact is that adjudication of sub-
- stantive due process claims may call upon the Court
- in interpreting the Constitution to exercise that same
- capacity which by tradition courts always have
- exercised: reasoned judgment.-
- Ante, at 7.
- Assuming that the question before us is to be resolved at
- such a level of philosophical abstraction, in such isolation
- from the traditions of American society, as by simply
- applying -reasoned judgment,- I do not see how that could
- possibly have produced the answer the Court arrived at in
- Roe v. Wade, 410 U. S. 113 (1973). Today's opinion de-
- scribes the methodology of Roe, quite accurately, as weigh-
- ing against the woman's interest the State's -`important
- and legitimate interest in protecting the potentiality of
- human life.'- Ante, at 28-29 (quoting Roe, supra, at 162).
- But -reasoned judgment- does not begin by begging the
- question, as Roe and subsequent cases unquestionably did
- by assuming that what the State is protecting is the mere
- -potentiality of human life.- See, e.g., Roe, supra, at 162;
- Planned Parenthood of Central Mo. v. Danforth, 428 U. S.
- 52, 61 (1976); Colautti v. Franklin, 439 U. S. 379, 386
- (1979); Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health, Inc.,
- 462 U. S. 416, 428 (1983) (Akron I); Planned Parenthood
- Assn. of Kansas City, Mo., Inc. v. Ashcroft, 462 U. S. 476,
- 482 (1983). The whole argument of abortion opponents is
- that what the Court calls the fetus and what others call the
- unborn child is a human life. Thus, whatever answer Roe
- came up with after conducting its -balancing- is bound to be
- wrong, unless it is correct that the human fetus is in some
- critical sense merely potentially human. There is of course
- no way to determine that as a legal matter; it is in fact a
- value judgment. Some societies have considered newborn
- children not yet human, or the incompetent elderly no
- longer so.
- The authors of the joint opinion, of course, do not square-
- ly contend that Roe v. Wade was a correct application of
- -reasoned judgment-; merely that it must be followed,
- because of stare decisis. Ante, at 11, 18-19, 29. But in
- their exhaustive discussion of all the factors that go into the
- determination of when stare decisis should be observed and
- when disregarded, they never mention -how wrong was the
- decision on its face?- Surely, if -[t]he Court's power lies . . .
- in its legitimacy, a product of substance and perception,-
- ante, at 23, the -substance- part of the equation demands
- that plain error be acknowledged and eliminated. Roe was
- plainly wrong-even on the Court's methodology of -rea-
- soned judgment,- and even more so (of course) if the proper
- criteria of text and tradition are applied.
- The emptiness of the -reasoned judgment- that produced
- Roe is displayed in plain view by the fact that, after more
- than 19 years of effort by some of the brightest (and most
- determined) legal minds in the country, after more than 10
- cases upholding abortion rights in this Court, and after
- dozens upon dozens of amicus briefs submitted in this and
- other cases, the best the Court can do to explain how it is
- that the word -liberty- must be thought to include the right
- to destroy human fetuses is to rattle off a collection of
- adjectives that simply decorate a value judgment and
- conceal a political choice. The right to abort, we are told,
- inheres in -liberty- because it is among -a person's most
- basic decisions,- ante, at 7; it involves a -most intimate and
- personal choic[e],- ante, at 9; it is -central to personal
- dignity and autonomy,- ibid.; it -originate[s] within the zone
- of conscience and belief,- ibid.; it is -too intimate and
- personal- for state interference, ante, at 10; it reflects
- -intimate views- of a -deep, personal character,- ante, at 11;
- it involves -intimate relationships,- and notions of -personal
- autonomy and bodily integrity,- ante, at 15; and it concerns
- a particularly -`important decisio[n],'- ante, at 16 (citation
- omitted). But it is obvious to anyone applying -reasoned
- judgment- that the same adjectives can be applied to many
- forms of conduct that this Court (including one of the
- Justices in today's majority, see Bowers v. Hardwick, 478
- U. S. 186 (1986)) has held are not entitled to constitutional
- protection-because, like abortion, they are forms of
- conduct that have long been criminalized in American
- society. Those adjectives might be applied, for example, to
- homosexual sodomy, polygamy, adult incest, and suicide, all
- of which are equally -intimate- and -deep[ly] personal-
- decisions involving -personal autonomy and bodily integri-
- ty,- and all of which can constitutionally be proscribed
- because it is our unquestionable constitutional tradition
- that they are proscribable. It is not reasoned judgment that
- supports the Court's decision; only personal predilection.
- Justice Curtis's warning is as timely today as it was 135
- years ago:
- -[W]hen a strict interpretation of the Constitution,
- according to the fixed rules which govern the interpre-
- tation of laws, is abandoned, and the theoretical
- opinions of individuals are allowed to control its
- meaning, we have no longer a Constitution; we are
- under the government of individual men, who for the
- time being have power to declare what the Constitution
- is, according to their own views of what it ought to
- mean.- Dred Scott v. Sandford, 19 How. 393, 621
- (1857) (Curtis, J., dissenting).
-
- -Liberty finds no refuge in a jurisprudence of doubt.-
- Ante, at 1.
- One might have feared to encounter this august and
- sonorous phrase in an opinion defending the real Roe v.
- Wade, rather than the revised version fabricated today by
- the authors of the joint opinion. The shortcomings of Roe
- did not include lack of clarity: Virtually all regulation of
- abortion before the third trimester was invalid. But to
- come across this phrase in the joint opinion-which calls
- upon federal district judges to apply an -undue burden-
- standard as doubtful in application as it is unprincipled in
- origin-is really more than one should have to bear.
- The joint opinion frankly concedes that the amorphous
- concept of -undue burden- has been inconsistently applied
- by the Members of this Court in the few brief years since
- that -test- was first explicitly propounded by Justice
- O'Connor in her dissent in Akron I, supra. See Ante,
- at 34. Because the three Justices now wish to -set forth a
- standard of general application,- the joint opinion announc-
- es that -it is important to clarify what is meant by an
- undue burden,- ibid. I certainly agree with that, but I do
- not agree that the joint opinion succeeds in the announced
- endeavor. To the contrary, its efforts at clarification make
- clear only that the standard is inherently manipulable and
- will prove hopelessly unworkable in practice.
- The joint opinion explains that a state regulation imposes
- an -undue burden- if it -has the purpose or effect of placing
- a substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking an
- abortion of a nonviable fetus.- Ibid.; see also ante, at
- 35-36. An obstacle is -substantial,- we are told, if it is
- -calculated[,] [not] to inform the woman's free choice, [but
- to] hinder it.- Ante, at 34. This latter statement cannot
- possibly mean what it says. Any regulation of abortion that
- is intended to advance what the joint opinion concedes is
- the State's -substantial- interest in protecting unborn life
- will be -calculated [to] hinder- a decision to have an
- abortion. It thus seems more accurate to say that the joint
- opinion would uphold abortion regulations only if they do
- not unduly hinder the woman's decision. That, of course,
- brings us right back to square one: Defining an -undue
- burden- as an -undue hindrance- (or a -substantial obsta-
- cle-) hardly -clarifies- the test. Consciously or not, the joint
- opinion's verbal shell game will conceal raw judicial policy
- choices concerning what is -appropriate- abortion legisla-
- tion.
- The ultimately standardless nature of the -undue burden-
- inquiry is a reflection of the underlying fact that the
- concept has no principled or coherent legal basis. As The
- Chief Justice points out, Roe's strict-scrutiny standard -at
- least had a recognized basis in constitutional law at the
- time Roe was decided,- ante, at 22, while -[t]he same cannot
- be said for the `undue burden' standard, which is created
- largely out of whole cloth by the authors of the joint
- opinion,- ibid. The joint opinion is flatly wrong in asserting
- that -our jurisprudence relating to all liberties save perhaps
- abortion has recognized- the permissibility of laws that do
- not impose an -undue burden.- Ante, at 31. It argues that
- the abortion right is similar to other rights in that a law
- -not designed to strike at the right itself, [but which] has
- the incidental effect of making it more difficult or more
- expensive to [exercise the right,]- is not invalid. Ante, at
- 31-32. I agree, indeed I have forcefully urged, that a law
- of general applicability which places only an incidental
- burden on a fundamental right does not infringe that right,
- see R. A. V. v. St. Paul, 505 U. S. ___, ___ (1992) (slip op.,
- at 11); Employment Division, Dept. of Human Resources of
- Ore. v. Smith, 494 U. S. 872, 878-882 (1990), but that
- principle does not establish the quite different (and quite
- dangerous) proposition that a law which directly regulates
- a fundamental right will not be found to violate the
- Constitution unless it imposes an -undue burden.- It is
- that, of course, which is at issue here: Pennsylvania has
- consciously and directly regulated conduct that our cases
- have held is constitutionally protected. The appropriate
- analogy, therefore, is that of a state law requiring purchas-
- ers of religious books to endure a 24-hour waiting period,
- or to pay a nominal additional tax of 1-. The joint opinion
- cannot possibly be correct in suggesting that we would
- uphold such legislation on the ground that it does not
- impose a -substantial obstacle- to the exercise of First
- Amendment rights. The -undue burden- standard is not at
- all the generally applicable principle the joint opinion
- pretends it to be; rather, it is a unique concept created
- specially for this case, to preserve some judicial foothold in
- this ill-gotten territory. In claiming otherwise, the three
- Justices show their willingness to place all constitutional
- rights at risk in an effort to preserve what they deem the
- -central holding in Roe,- ante, at 31.
- The rootless nature of the -undue burden- standard, a
- phrase plucked out of context from our earlier abortion
- decisions, see n. 3, supra, is further reflected in the fact
- that the joint opinion finds it necessary expressly to
- repudiate the more narrow formulations used in Justice
- O'Connor's earlier opinions. Ante, at 35. Those opinions
- stated that a statute imposes an -undue burden- if it
- imposes -absolute obstacles or severe limitations on the
- abortion decision,- Akron I, 462 U. S., at 464 (O'Connor, J.,
- dissenting) (emphasis added); see also Thornburgh v.
- American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, 476
- U. S. 747, 828 (1986) (O'Connor, J., dissenting). Those
- strong adjectives are conspicuously missing from the joint
- opinion, whose authors have for some unexplained reason
- now determined that a burden is -undue- if it merely
- imposes a -substantial- obstacle to abortion decisions. See,
- e.g., ante, at 53, 59. Justice O'Connor has also aban-
- doned (again without explanation) the view she expressed
- in Planned Parenthood Assn. of Kansas City, Mo., Inc. v.
- Ashcroft, 462 U. S. 476 (1983) (dissenting opinion), that a
- medical regulation which imposes an -undue burden- could
- nevertheless be upheld if it -reasonably relate[s] to the
- preservation and protection of maternal health,- id., at 505
- (citation and internal quotation marks omitted). In today's
- version, even health measures will be upheld only -if they
- do not constitute an undue burden,- ante, at 35 (emphasis
- added). Gone too is Justice O'Connor's statement that
- -the State possesses compelling interests in the protection
- of potential human life . . . throughout pregnancy,- Akron
- I, supra, at 461 (emphasis added); see also Ashcroft, supra,
- at 505 (O'Connor, J., concurring in judgment in part and
- dissenting in part); Thornburgh, supra, at 828 (O'Connor,
- J., dissenting); instead, the State's interest in unborn
- human life is stealthily downgraded to a merely -substan-
- tial- or -profound- interest, ante, at 34, 36. (That had to be
- done, of course, since designating the interest as -compel-
- ling- throughout pregnancy would have been, shall we say,
- a -substantial obstacle- to the joint opinion's determined
- effort to reaffirm what it views as the -central holding- of
- Roe. See Akron I, 462 U. S., at 420, n. 1.) And -viability-
- is no longer the -arbitrary- dividing line previously decried
- by Justice O'Connor in Akron I, id., at 461; the Court now
- announces that -the attainment of viability may continue to
- serve as the critical fact,- ante, at 18. It is difficult to
- maintain the illusion that we are interpreting a Constitu-
- tion rather than inventing one, when we amend its provi-
- sions so breezily.
- Because the portion of the joint opinion adopting and
- describing the undue-burden test provides no more useful
- guidance than the empty phrases discussed above, one must
- turn to the 23 pages applying that standard to the present
- facts for further guidance. In evaluating Pennsylvania's
- abortion law, the joint opinion relies extensively on the
- factual findings of the District Court, and repeatedly
- qualifies its conclusions by noting that they are contingent
- upon the record developed in this case. Thus, the joint
- opinion would uphold the 24-hour waiting period contained
- in the Pennsylvania statute's informed consent provision, 18
- Pa. Cons. Stat. 3205 (1990), because -the record evidence
- shows that in the vast majority of cases, a 24-hour delay
- does not create any appreciable health risk,- ante, at 43.
- The three Justices therefore conclude that -on the record
- before us, . . . we are not convinced that the 24-hour
- waiting period constitutes an undue burden.- Ante, at
- 44-45. The requirement that a doctor provide the informa-
- tion pertinent to informed consent would also be upheld
- because -there is no evidence on this record that [this
- requirement] would amount in practical terms to a substan-
- tial obstacle to a woman seeking an abortion,- ante, at 42.
- Similarly, the joint opinion would uphold the reporting
- requirements of the Act, 3207, 3214, because -there is no
- . . . showing on the record before us- that these require-
- ments constitute a -substantial obstacle- to abortion
- decisions. Ante, at 59. But at the same time the opinion
- pointedly observes that these reporting requirements may
- increase the costs of abortions and that -at some point [that
- fact] could become a substantial obstacle,- ibid. Most
- significantly, the joint opinion's conclusion that the spousal
- notice requirement of the Act, see 3209, imposes an
- -undue burden- is based in large measure on the District
- Court's -detailed findings of fact,- which the joint opinion
- sets out at great length. Ante, at 45-49.
- I do not, of course, have any objection to the notion that,
- in applying legal principles, one should rely only upon the
- facts that are contained in the record or that are properly
- subject to judicial notice. But what is remarkable about
- the joint opinion's fact-intensive analysis is that it does not
- result in any measurable clarification of the -undue burden-
- standard. Rather, the approach of the joint opinion is, for
- the most part, simply to highlight certain facts in the record
- that apparently strike the three Justices as particularly
- significant in establishing (or refuting) the existence of an
- undue burden; after describing these facts, the opinion then
- simply announces that the provision either does or does not
- impose a -substantial obstacle- or an -undue burden.- See,
- e.g., ante, at 38, 42, 44-45, 45, 52, 53, 59. We do not know
- whether the same conclusions could have been reached on
- a different record, or in what respects the record would
- have had to differ before an opposite conclusion would have
- been appropriate. The inherently standardless nature of
- this inquiry invites the district judge to give effect to his
- personal preferences about abortion. By finding and relying
- upon the right facts, he can invalidate, it would seem,
- almost any abortion restriction that strikes him as -un-
- due--subject, of course, to the possibility of being reversed
- by a Circuit Court or Supreme Court that is as uncon-
- strained in reviewing his decision as he was in making it.
- To the extent I can discern any meaningful content in the
- -undue burden- standard as applied in the joint opinion, it
- appears to be that a State may not regulate abortion in
- such a way as to reduce significantly its incidence. The
- joint opinion repeatedly emphasizes that an important
- factor in the -undue burden- analysis is whether the
- regulation -prevent[s] a significant number of women from
- obtaining an abortion,- ante, at 52; whether a -significant
- number of women . . . are likely to be deterred from
- procuring an abortion,- ibid.; and whether the regulation
- often -deters- women from seeking abortions, ante, at
- 55-56. We are not told, however, what forms of -deter-
- rence- are impermissible or what degree of success in
- deterrence is too much to be tolerated. If, for example, a
- State required a woman to read a pamphlet describing,
- with illustrations, the facts of fetal development before she
- could obtain an abortion, the effect of such legislation might
- be to -deter- a -significant number of women- from procur-
- ing abortions, thereby seemingly allowing a district judge to
- invalidate it as an undue burden. Thus, despite flowery
- rhetoric about the State's -substantial- and -profound-
- interest in -potential human life,- and criticism of Roe for
- undervaluing that interest, the joint opinion permits the
- State to pursue that interest only so long as it is not too
- successful. As Justice Blackmun recognizes (with evident
- hope), ante, at 5, the -undue burden- standard may ulti-
- mately require the invalidation of each provision upheld
- today if it can be shown, on a better record, that the State
- is too effectively -express[ing] a preference for childbirth
- over abortion,- ante, at 41. Reason finds no refuge in this
- jurisprudence of confusion.
-
- -While we appreciate the weight of the arguments
- . . . that Roe should be overruled, the reservations
- any of us may have in reaffirming the central holding
- of Roe are outweighed by the explication of individu-
- al liberty we have given combined with the force of
- stare decisis.-
- Ante, at 11.
- The Court's reliance upon stare decisis can best be
- described as contrived. It insists upon the necessity of
- adhering not to all of Roe, but only to what it calls the
- -central holding.- It seems to me that stare decisis ought to
- be applied even to the doctrine of stare decisis, and I confess
- never to have heard of this new, keep-what-you-want-and-
- throw-away-the-rest version. I wonder whether, as applied
- to Marbury v. Madison, 1 Cranch 137 (1803), for example,
- the new version of stare decisis would be satisfied if we
- allowed courts to review the constitutionality of only those
- statutes that (like the one in Marbury) pertain to the
- jurisdiction of the courts.
- I am certainly not in a good position to dispute that the
- Court has saved the -central holding- of Roe, since to do
- that effectively I would have to know what the Court has
- saved, which in turn would require me to understand (as I
- do not) what the -undue burden- test means. I must
- confess, however, that I have always thought, and I think
- a lot of other people have always thought, that the arbi-
- trary trimester framework, which the Court today discards,
- was quite as central to Roe as the arbitrary viability test,
- which the Court today retains. It seems particularly
- ungrateful to carve the trimester framework out of the core
- of Roe, since its very rigidity (in sharp contrast to the utter
- indeterminability of the -undue burden- test) is probably
- the only reason the Court is able to say, in urging stare
- decisis, that Roe -has in no sense proven `unworkable,'-
- ante, at 13. I suppose the Court is entitled to call a -cen-
- tral holding- whatever it wants to call a -central hold-
- ing--which is, come to think of it, perhaps one of the
- difficulties with this modified version of stare decisis. I
- thought I might note, however, that the following portions
- of Roe have not been saved:
- -Under Roe, requiring that a woman seeking an abortion
- be provided truthful information about abortion before
- giving informed written consent is unconstitutional, if the
- information is designed to influence her choice, Thornburgh,
- 476 U. S., at 759-765; Akron I, 462 U. S., at 442-445.
- Under the joint opinion's -undue burden- regime (as applied
- today, at least) such a requirement is constitutional, ante,
- at 38-42.
- -Under Roe, requiring that information be provided by a
- doctor, rather than by nonphysician counselors, is unconsti-
- tutional, Akron I, supra, at 446-449. Under the -undue
- burden- regime (as applied today, at least) it is not, ante,
- at 42.
- -Under Roe, requiring a 24-hour waiting period between
- the time the woman gives her informed consent and the
- time of the abortion is unconstitutional, Akron I, supra, at
- 449-451. Under the -undue burden- regime (as applied
- today, at least) it is not, ante, at 43-45.
- -Under Roe, requiring detailed reports that include
- demographic data about each woman who seeks an abortion
- and various information about each abortion is unconstitu-
- tional, Thornburgh, supra, at 765-768. Under the -undue
- burden- regime (as applied today, at least) it generally is
- not, ante, at 58-59.
-
- -Where, in the performance of its judicial duties,
- the Court decides a case in such a way as to resolve
- the sort of intensely divisive controversy reflected in
- Roe . . . , its decision has a dimension that the resolu-
- tion of the normal case does not carry. It is the
- dimension present whenever the Court's interpreta-
- tion of the Constitution calls the contending sides of
- a national controversy to end their national division
- by accepting a common mandate rooted in the
- Constitution.-
- Ante, at 24.
- The Court's description of the place of Roe in the social
- history of the United States is unrecognizable. Not only did
- Roe not, as the Court suggests, resolve the deeply divisive
- issue of abortion; it did more than anything else to nourish
- it, by elevating it to the national level where it is infinitely
- more difficult to resolve. National politics were not plagued
- by abortion protests, national abortion lobbying, or abortion
- marches on Congress, before Roe v. Wade was decided.
- Profound disagreement existed among our citizens over the
- issue-as it does over other issues, such as the death
- penalty-but that disagreement was being worked out at
- the state level. As with many other issues, the division of
- sentiment within each State was not as closely balanced as
- it was among the population of the Nation as a whole,
- meaning not only that more people would be satisfied with
- the results of state-by-state resolution, but also that those
- results would be more stable. Pre-Roe, moreover, political
- compromise was possible.
- Roe's mandate for abortion-on-demand destroyed the
- compromises of the past, rendered compromise impossible
- for the future, and required the entire issue to be resolved
- uniformly, at the national level. At the same time, Roe
- created a vast new class of abortion consumers and abortion
- proponents by eliminating the moral opprobrium that had
- attached to the act. (-If the Constitution guarantees abor-
- tion, how can it be bad?--not an accurate line of thought,
- but a natural one.) Many favor all of those developments,
- and it is not for me to say that they are wrong. But to
- portray Roe as the statesmanlike -settlement- of a divisive
- issue, a jurisprudential Peace of Westphalia that is worth
- preserving, is nothing less than Orwellian. Roe fanned into
- life an issue that has inflamed our national politics in
- general, and has obscured with its smoke the selection of
- Justices to this Court in particular, ever since. And by
- keeping us in the abortion-umpiring business, it is the
- perpetuation of that disruption, rather than of any pax
- Roeana, that the Court's new majority decrees.
-
- -[T]o overrule under fire . . . would subvert the
- Court's legitimacy . . . .
- -To all those who will be . . . tested by following, the
- Court implicitly undertakes to remain steadfast . . . .
- The promise of constancy, once given, binds its
- maker for as long as the power to stand by the
- decision survives and . . . the commitment [is not]
- obsolete. . . .
- -[The American people's] belief in themselves as . . .
- a people [who aspire to live according to the rule of
- law] is not readily separable from their understand-
- ing of the Court invested with the authority to decide
- their constitutional cases and speak before all others
- for their constitutional ideals. If the Court's legitima-
- cy should be undermined, then, so would the country
- be in its very ability to see itself through its constitu-
- tional ideals.-
- Ante, at 25-26.
- The Imperial Judiciary lives. It is instructive to compare
- this Nietzschean vision of us unelected, life-tenured
- judges-leading a Volk who will be -tested by following,-
- and whose very -belief in themselves- is mystically bound
- up in their -understanding- of a Court that -speak[s] before
- all others for their constitutional ideals--with the some-
- what more modest role envisioned for these lawyers by the
- Founders.
- -The judiciary . . . has . . . no direction either of the
- strength or of the wealth of the society, and can take
- no active resolution whatever. It may truly be said to
- have neither Force nor Will but merely judgment
- . . . .- The Federalist No. 78, pp. 393-394 (G. Wills ed.
- 1982).
- Or, again, to compare this ecstasy of a Supreme Court in
- which there is, especially on controversial matters, no
- shadow of change or hint of alteration (-There is a limit to
- the amount of error that can plausibly be imputed to prior
- courts,- ante, at 24), with the more democratic views of a
- more humble man:
- -[T]he candid citizen must confess that if the policy of
- the Government upon vital questions affecting the
- whole people is to be irrevocably fixed by decisions of
- the Supreme Court, . . . the people will have ceased to
- be their own rulers, having to that extent practically
- resigned their Government into the hands of that
- eminent tribunal.- A. Lincoln, First Inaugural Address
- (Mar. 4, 1861), reprinted in Inaugural Addresses of the
- Presidents of the United States, S. Doc. No. 101-10,
- p. 139 (1989).
- It is particularly difficult, in the circumstances of the
- present decision, to sit still for the Court's lengthy lecture
- upon the virtues of -constancy,- ante, at 26, of -remain[ing]
- steadfast,- id., at 25, of adhering to -principle,- id., passim.
- Among the five Justices who purportedly adhere to Roe, at
- most three agree upon the principle that constitutes
- adherence (the joint opinion's -undue burden- stan-
- dard)-and that principle is inconsistent with Roe, see 410
- U. S., at 154-156. To make matters worse, two of the
- three, in order thus to remain steadfast, had to abandon
- previously stated positions. See n. 4 supra; see supra, at
- 11-12. It is beyond me how the Court expects these
- accommodations to be accepted -as grounded truly in
- principle, not as compromises with social and political
- pressures having, as such, no bearing on the principled
- choices that the Court is obliged to make.- Ante, at 23.
- The only principle the Court -adheres- to, it seems to me,
- is the principle that the Court must be seen as standing by
- Roe. That is not a principle of law (which is what I thought
- the Court was talking about), but a principle of Realpoli-
- tik-and a wrong one at that.
- I cannot agree with, indeed I am appalled by, the Court's
- suggestion that the decision whether to stand by an
- erroneous constitutional decision must be strongly influ-
- enced-against overruling, no less-by the substantial and
- continuing public opposition the decision has generated.
- The Court's judgment that any other course would -subvert
- the Court's legitimacy- must be another consequence of
- reading the error-filled history book that described the
- deeply divided country brought together by Roe. In my
- history-book, the Court was covered with dishonor and
- deprived of legitimacy by Dred Scott v. Sandford, 19 How.
- 393 (1857), an erroneous (and widely opposed) opinion that
- it did not abandon, rather than by West Coast Hotel Co. v.
- Parrish, 300 U. S. 379 (1937), which produced the famous
- -switch in time- from the Court's erroneous (and widely
- opposed) constitutional opposition to the social measures of
- the New Deal. (Both Dred Scott and one line of the cases
- resisting the New Deal rested upon the concept of -substan-
- tive due process- that the Court praises and employs today.
- Indeed, Dred Scott was -very possibly the first application
- of substantive due process in the Supreme Court, the
- original precedent for Lochner v. New York and Roe v.
- Wade.- D. Currie, The Constitution in the Supreme Court
- 271 (1985) (footnotes omitted).)
- But whether it would -subvert the Court's legitimacy- or
- not, the notion that we would decide a case differently from
- the way we otherwise would have in order to show that we
- can stand firm against public disapproval is frightening. It
- is a bad enough idea, even in the head of someone like me,
- who believes that the text of the Constitution, and our
- traditions, say what they say and there is no fiddling with
- them. But when it is in the mind of a Court that believes
- the Constitution has an evolving meaning, see ante, at 6;
- that the Ninth Amendment's reference to -othe[r]- rights is
- not a disclaimer, but a charter for action, ibid.; and that the
- function of this Court is to -speak before all others for [the
- people's] constitutional ideals- unrestrained by meaningful
- text or tradition-then the notion that the Court must
- adhere to a decision for as long as the decision faces -great
- opposition- and the Court is -under fire- acquires a charac-
- ter of almost czarist arrogance. We are offended by these
- marchers who descend upon us, every year on the anniver-
- sary of Roe, to protest our saying that the Constitution
- requires what our society has never thought the Constitu-
- tion requires. These people who refuse to be -tested by
- following- must be taught a lesson. We have no Cossacks,
- but at least we can stubbornly refuse to abandon an
- erroneous opinion that we might otherwise change-to show
- how little they intimidate us.
- Of course, as the Chief Justice points out, we have been
- subjected to what the Court calls -political pressure- by
- both sides of this issue. Ante, at 21. Maybe today's
- decision not to overrule Roe will be seen as buckling to
- pressure from that direction. Instead of engaging in the
- hopeless task of predicting public perception-a job not for
- lawyers but for political campaign managers-the Justices
- should do what is legally right by asking two questions:
- (1) Was Roe correctly decided? (2) Has Roe succeeded in
- producing a settled body of law? If the answer to both
- questions is no, Roe should undoubtedly be overruled.
- In truth, I am as distressed as the Court is-and ex-
- pressed my distress several years ago, see Webster, 492
- U. S., at 535-about the -political pressure- directed to the
- Court: the marches, the mail, the protests aimed at induc-
- ing us to change our opinions. How upsetting it is, that so
- many of our citizens (good people, not lawless ones, on both
- sides of this abortion issue, and on various sides of other
- issues as well) think that we Justices should properly take
- into account their views, as though we were engaged not in
- ascertaining an objective law but in determining some kind
- of social consensus. The Court would profit, I think, from
- giving less attention to the fact of this distressing phenome-
- non, and more attention to the cause of it. That cause
- permeates today's opinion: a new mode of constitutional
- adjudication that relies not upon text and traditional
- practice to determine the law, but upon what the Court
- calls -reasoned judgment,- ante, at 7, which turns out to be
- nothing but philosophical predilection and moral intuition.
- All manner of -liberties,- the Court tells us, inhere in the
- Constitution and are enforceable by this Court-not just
- those mentioned in the text or established in the traditions
- of our society. Ante, at 5-6. Why even the Ninth Amend-
- ment-which says only that -[t]he enumeration in the
- Constitution of certain rights shall not be construed to deny
- or disparage others retained by the people--is, despite our
- contrary understanding for almost 200 years, a literally
- boundless source of additional, unnamed, unhinted-at
- -rights,- definable and enforceable by us, through -reasoned
- judgment.- Ante, at 6-7.
- What makes all this relevant to the bothersome applica-
- tion of -political pressure- against the Court are the twin
- facts that the American people love democracy and the
- American people are not fools. As long as this Court
- thought (and the people thought) that we Justices were
- doing essentially lawyers' work up here-reading text and
- discerning our society's traditional understanding of that
- text-the public pretty much left us alone. Texts and
- traditions are facts to study, not convictions to demonstrate
- about. But if in reality our process of constitutional
- adjudication consists primarily of making value judgments;
- if we can ignore a long and clear tradition clarifying an
- ambiguous text, as we did, for example, five days ago in
- declaring unconstitutional invocations and benedictions at
- public-high-school graduation ceremonies, Lee v. Weisman,
- 505 U. S. ___ (1992); if, as I say, our pronouncement of
- constitutional law rests primarily on value judgments, then
- a free and intelligent people's attitude towards us can be
- expected to be (ought to be) quite different. The people
- know that their value judgments are quite as good as those
- taught in any law school-maybe better. If, indeed, the
- -liberties- protected by the Constitution are, as the Court
- says, undefined and unbounded, then the people should
- demonstrate, to protest that we do not implement their
- values instead of ours. Not only that, but confirmation
- hearings for new Justices should deteriorate into question-
- and-answer sessions in which Senators go through a list of
- their constituents' most favored and most disfavored alleged
- constitutional rights, and seek the nominee's commitment
- to support or oppose them. Value judgments, after all,
- should be voted on, not dictated; and if our Constitution has
- somehow accidently committed them to the Supreme Court,
- at least we can have a sort of plebiscite each time a new
- nominee to that body is put forward. Justice Blackmun
- not only regards this prospect with equanimity, he solicits
- it, ante, at 22-23.
- * * *
- There is a poignant aspect to today's opinion. Its length,
- and what might be called its epic tone, suggest that its
- authors believe they are bringing to an end a troublesome
- era in the history of our Nation and of our Court. -It is the
- dimension- of authority, they say, to -cal[l] the contending
- sides of national controversy to end their national division
- by accepting a common mandate rooted in the Constitu-
- tion.- Ante, at 24.
- There comes vividly to mind a portrait by Emanuel
- Leutze that hangs in the Harvard Law School: Roger
- Brooke Taney, painted in 1859, the 82d year of his life, the
- 24th of his Chief Justiceship, the second after his opinion
- in Dred Scott. He is all in black, sitting in a shadowed red
- armchair, left hand resting upon a pad of paper in his lap,
- right hand hanging limply, almost lifelessly, beside the
- inner arm of the chair. He sits facing the viewer, and
- staring straight out. There seems to be on his face, and in
- his deep-set eyes, an expression of profound sadness and
- disillusionment. Perhaps he always looked that way, even
- when dwelling upon the happiest of thoughts. But those of
- us who know how the lustre of his great Chief Justiceship
- came to be eclipsed by Dred Scott cannot help believing that
- he had that case-its already apparent consequences for the
- Court, and its soon-to-be-played-out consequences for the
- Nation-burning on his mind. I expect that two years
- earlier he, too, had thought himself -call[ing] the contend-
- ing sides of national controversy to end their national
- division by accepting a common mandate rooted in the
- Constitution.-
- It is no more realistic for us in this case, than it was for
- him in that, to think that an issue of the sort they both
- involved-an issue involving life and death, freedom and
- subjugation-can be -speedily and finally settled- by the
- Supreme Court, as President James Buchanan in his
- inaugural address said the issue of slavery in the territories
- would be. See Inaugural Addresses of the Presidents of the
- United States, S. Doc. No. 101-10, p. 126 (1989). Quite to
- the contrary, by foreclosing all democratic outlet for the
- deep passions this issue arouses, by banishing the issue
- from the political forum that gives all participants, even the
- losers, the satisfaction of a fair hearing and an honest fight,
- by continuing the imposition of a rigid national rule instead
- of allowing for regional differences, the Court merely
- prolongs and intensifies the anguish.
- We should get out of this area, where we have no right to
- be, and where we do neither ourselves nor the country any
- good by remaining.
-